|
Bertrand Russell
The Twilight of Science
Is the Universe Running Down?
It is a curious fact that just when the man in the street has begun to believe
thoroughly in science, the man in the laboratory has begun to lose his faith,
When I was young, no physicist entertained the slightest doubt that the laws of
physics give us real information about the motions of bodies, and that the
physical world does really consist of the sort of entities that appear in the
physicist's equations. The philosophers, it is true, throw doubt upon this
view, and have done so ever since the time of Berkeley; but since their
criticism never attached itself to any point in the detailed procedure of
science, it could be ignored by scientists and was in fact ignored. Nowadays
matters are quite different; the revolutionary ideas of the philosophy of
physics have come from the physicists themselves and are the outcome of careful
experiments.
The new philosophy of physics is humble and stammering where the old philosophy
was proud and dictatorial. It is, I suppose, natural to every man to fill the
vacuum left by the disappearance of belief in physical laws as best he may, and
to use for this purpose any odds and ends of unfounded belief which had
previously no room to expand. When the robustness of the Catholic faith decayed
at the time of the Renaissance, it tended to be replaced by astrology and
necromancy, and in like manner we must expect the decay of the scientific faith
to lead to a recrudescence of pre-scientific superstitions.
Whoever wishes to know how and why, scientific faith is decaying cannot do
better than read Eddington's ton's Gifford lecturer, entitled "The Nature
of the Physical World." He will learn there that physics is divided into
three departments. The first contains all the classical physics, such as the
conservation of energy and momentum, and the Jaw of gravitation. All these
according to Professor Eddington boil down to nothing but conventions as to
measurement true, the laws they state are universal, but so is the law that
there are three feet in a yard, which, according to him, is just as informative
concerning the course of nature. The second department of physics is concerned
with large aggregates, and the laws of chance. Here we, do not attempt to prove
that such and such an event is impossible, but only that it is wildly
improbable. The third department of physics, which is the most modern, is the
quantum theory, and this is the most disturbing of all since it seems to show
that the law of causality, in which science has hitherto implicitly believed,
cannot be applied to the doings of individual electrons. I shall say a few
words about each of these three matters in turn.
To begin with classical physics. Newton's law of gravitation, as every one
knows, was somewhat modified by Einstein, and the modification was
experimentally confirmed. But if Eddington's view is right, this experimental,
confirmation does not have the signification that one would naturally attribute
to it. After considering three possible views as to what the law of gravitation
assert about the motion of the earth round the sun, Eddington plumps for a
fourth, to the effect that " the earth goes anyhow it likes," that is
to say, that the law of gravitation tells us absolutely nothing about the way
the earth moves. He admits that this view is paradoxical, but he says:
"The key to the paradox is that we ourselves, our conventions, the kind of
thing that attracts our interest, are much more concerned than we realize in
any account we give of how the objects of the physical world are behaving. And
so an object which, viewed through our frame of conventions, may seem to be
behaving in a very special and remarkable way may, viewed according to another
set of conventions, be doing nothing to excite particular comment. "
I must confess that I find this view a very difficult one; respect for
Eddington prevents me from. saying that it is, untrue, but there are various
points in his argument which I have difficulty in following. Of course all the
practical consequences which we deduce from the abstract theory, as for example
that we shall perceive daylight at certain times and not at certain other
times, lie outside the scheme of official physics, which never reach our
sensations at all. I cannot but suspect, however, that official physics is just
a little bit too official in Eddington's hands, and that it would not be
impossible to allow it a little more significance than it has in his
interpretation. However that may be, it is an important sign of the times that
one of the leading exponents of scientific theory should advance so modest an
opinion.
I come now to the statistical part of physics which is concerned with the study
of large aggregates. Large aggregates behave almost exactly as they were
supposed to do before the quantum theory was invented, so that in regard to
them the older physics is very nearly right. There is, however, one supremely
important law which is only statistical; this is the second law of
thermodynamics. It states, roughly speaking, that the world is growing
continuously more disorderly.
Eddington illustrates it by what happens when you shuffle a pack of cards. The
pack of cards comes from the makers with the cards arranged in their proper
order; after you have shuffled them, this order is lost, and it is in the
highest degree improbable that it will ever be restored by subsequent
shuffling. It is this sort of thing that makes the difference between past and
future. In the rest of theoretical physics we are dealing with processes that
are reversible; that is to say, where the laws of physics show that it is
possible for amaterial system to pass from state A at one time to state B at
another, the opposite transition will be equally possible according to these
same laws; but where the second law of thermodynamics comes in, this is not the
case. Professor Eddington enunciates the law as follows: "Whenever
anything happens that cannot be undone, it is always reducible to the
introduction of a random element analogous to that introduced by
,shuffling." This law, unlike most of the laws of physics, is concerned
only with probabilities. To take our previous illustration: it is of course
possible that, if you shuffle a pack of cards long enough, the cards may happen
to get into the right order by chance. This is very unlikely, but it is far
less unlikely than the orderly arrangement of many millions of molecules by
chance. Professor Eddington gives the following illustration: suppose a vessel
divided into two equal parts by a partition, and suppose that in one part there
is air, while in the other there is a vacuum; then a door in the partition is
opened and the air spreads itself evenly throughout the whole vessel. It might
happen by chance that at some future time the moleculesthe air in the course of
their random movements would all find themselves again in the partitions in
which they originally were. This is not impossible; it is only improbable, but
it is improbable.
"If I let my fingers wander idly over the keys of a typewriter it might
happen that my screed made an intelligible sentence. If an army of monkeys were
strumming on typewriters they might write all the books in the British Museum.
The chance of their doing so is decidedly more favorable than the chance of the
molecules returning to one half of the vessel."
There are an immense number of illustrations of the same kind of thing. For
example, if you drop one drop of ink into a glass of clear water, it will
gradually diffuse itself throughout the glass. It might happen by chance that
it would afterwards collect itself again into a drop, but we should certainly
regard it as a miracle if it happened. When a hot body and a cold body are put
in contact, we all know that the hot body cools and the cold body gets warm
until the two reach the same temperature, but this also is only a law of
probability. It might happen that a kettle filled with water put on the fire
would freeze instead of boil; this also is not shown to be impossible by any of
the laws of physics, it is only shown to be highly improbable by the second law
of thermodynamics. This law states, speaking generally, that the universe tends
toward democracy, and that when it has achieved that state, it will be
incapable of doing anything more. It seems that the world was created at some
not infinitely remote date, and was then far more full of. inequalities than it
is now; but from the moment of creation it has been continually running down,
and will ultimately stop for all practical purposesunless it is again wound up.
Professor Eddington for some reason does not like the idea that it can be wound
up again, but prefers to think that the world drama is only to be performed
once, in spite of the fact that it must end in aeons of boredom, in the course
of which the whole audience will gradually go to sleep.
Quantum theory, which is concerned with individual atoms and electrons, is
still in a state of rapid development, and is probably far from its final form.
In the hands of Heisenberg, Schrodinger and Co., it has become more disturbing
and more revolutionary than the theory of relativity ever was. Professor
Eddington expounds its recent developments in a manner which conveys more of it
to the non-mathematical reader than I should have supposed possible. It is
profoundly disturbing to the prejudices which have governed physics since the
time of Newton. The most painful thing about it from this point of view is
that, as mentioned above, it throws doubt upon the universality of causality;
the view at present is that atoms have a certain amount of free-will, so that
their behavior even in theory, is not wholly subject to law. Moreover, some
things which we thought definite, at least in theory, have quite ceased to be
so. There is what Eddington calls the "principle of indeterminancy";
this states that "a particle may have position or it may have velocity,
but it cannot in any exact sense have both," that is to say, if you know
where you are, you cannot tell how fast you are moving, and if you know how
fast you are moving, you cannot tell where you are. This cuts at the root of
traditional physics, in which position and velocity were fundamental. You can
only see an electron when it emits light, and it only emits light when it
jumps, so that to see where it was, you have to make it go elsewhere. This
breakdown of physical determinism is utilized by Eddington in his concluding
chapters to rehabilitate free-will.
Professor Eddington proceeds to base optimistic and pleasant conclusions upon
the scientific nescience which he has expounded in previous pages. This
optimism based uponthe time- honored principle that any. thing which cannot be
proved untrue may be assumed to be true a principle whose falsehood is proved
by the fortunes of bookmakers. If we discard this principle, it is difficult to
see what ground for cheerfulness modern physics provides. It tells us that the
universe is running down, and if Eddington is right, it tells us practically
nothing else, since all the. rest is merely the rules of the game. From a
pragmatic or political point of view probably the most important thing about
such a theory of physics is that it will destroy, if it becomes widespread,
that faith in science which has been the only constructive creed of modern
times, and the source of virtually all change both for good and for evil. The
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries had a philosophy of natural law based upon
Newton. The law was supposed to imply a Lawgiver, though as time went on this
inference was less emphasized; but in any case the universe was orderly and
predictable. By learning nature's laws we could hope to manipulate nature, and
thus science became the source of power, This is still the outlook of most
energetic practical men, but it Is no longer the outlook of men of science. The
world according to them i's a more higgledy-piggledy and haphazard affair than
it was thought to be. And they know much less about it than was thought to be
known by, their predecessors in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.
Perhaps the scientific skepticism of which Eddington is an exponent may lead in
the end to the collapse of the scientific era, just as the theological
skepticism of the Renaissance has led gradually to the collapse of the
theological era. I suppose that machines will survive the collapse of science,
just as parsons have survived the collapse of theology, but in the one case as
in the other they will cease to be viewed with reverence and awe. Perhaps this
is not to be regretted.
|